叠测听听补苍诲 , Lecturers in Law.
The fear of powerful artificial intelligence and technology is a popular theme, as seen in films such as , , and the series.
And we may soon find ourselves addressing fully autonomous technology with the capacity to cause damage. While this may be some form of military wardroid or law enforcement robot, it could equally be something not created to cause harm, but which could nevertheless do so by accident or error. What then? Who is culpable and liable when a robot or artificial intelligence goes haywire? Clearly, our way of approaching this doesn鈥檛 neatly fit into society鈥檚 view of guilt and justice.
While some may choose to dismiss this as too far into the future to concern us, remember that a robot has already . This also ignores how quickly technology can evolve. Look at the lessons from the past 鈥 many of us still remember the world before the internet, social media, mobile technology, GPS 鈥 even phones or widely available computers. These once-dramatic innovations developed into everyday technologies which have created difficult legal challenges.
A guilty robot mind?
How quickly we take technology for granted. But we should give some thought to the legal implications. One of the functions of our legal system is to regulate the behaviour of legal persons and to punish and deter offenders. It also provides remedies for those who have suffered, or are at risk of suffering harm.
Legal persons 鈥 humans, but also companies and other organisations 鈥 are subject to rights and responsibilities. Those who design, operate, build or sell intelligent machines have legal duties 鈥 what about the machines themselves? Our mobile phone, even with Cortana or Siri attached, does not fit the conventions for a legal person. But what if the autonomous decisions of their more advanced descendents in the future cause harm or damage?
Criminal law has two important concepts. First, that liability arises when harm has been or is likely to be caused by any act or omission. Physical devices such as Google鈥檚 driverless car, for example, clearly has the potential to harm, kill or damage property. Software also has the potential to cause physical harm, but the risks may extend to less immediate forms of damage such as financial loss.
Second, criminal law often requires culpability in the offender, what is known as the 鈥済uilty mind鈥 or mens rea 鈥 the principle being that the offence, and subsequent punishment, reflects the offender鈥檚 state of mind and role in proceedings. This generally means that deliberate actions are punished more severely than careless ones. This poses a problem, in terms of treating autonomous intelligent machines under the law: how do we demonstrate the intentions of a non-human, and how can we do this within existing criminal law principles?
Robocrime?
This isn鈥檛 a new problem 鈥 similar considerations arise in trials of corporate criminality. Some thought needs to go into when, and in what circumstances, we make the designer or manufacturer liable rather than the user. Much of our current law assumes that human operators are involved.
For example, in the context of highways, the regulatory framework assumes that there is a human driver to at least some degree. Once fully autonomous vehicles arrive, that framework will require substantial changes to address the new interactions between human and machine on the road.
As intelligent technology that by-passes direct human control becomes more advanced and more widespread, these questions of risk, fault and punishment will become more pertinent. Film and television may dwell on the most extreme examples, but the legal realities are best not left to fiction.
Jeffrey Wale and David Yuratich will be talking about these issues in their free Festival of Learning workshop聽on聽成人直播's聽Talbot Campus on Wednesday 15 July 2015 at 6pm. For more information and to book, visit the webpages.
This article was originally published on . Read the .